1
|
|
2
|
- Reducing first-order inference to propositional inference
- Unification
- Generalized Modus Ponens
- Forward chaining
- Backward chaining
- Resolution
|
3
|
- Every instantiation of a universally quantified sentence is entailed by
it:
- "v α
Subst({v/g}, α)
- for any variable v and ground term g
- E.g., "x King(x) Ù Greedy(x) Þ Evil(x) yields:
- King(John) Ù Greedy(John) Þ
Evil(John)
- King(Richard) Ù Greedy(Richard)
Þ Evil(Richard)
- King(Father(John)) Ù Greedy(Father(John))
Þ Evil(Father(John))
- .
- .
- .
|
4
|
- For any sentence α, variable v, and constant symbol k that does not
appear elsewhere in the knowledge base:
- $v α
- Subst({v/k}, α)
- E.g., $x Crown(x) Ù OnHead(x,John) yields:
- Crown(C1) Ù OnHead(C1,John)
- provided C1 is a new constant symbol, called a Skolem
constant
|
5
|
- Suppose the KB contains just the following:
- "x King(x) Ù Greedy(x) Þ Evil(x)
- King(John)
- Greedy(John)
- Brother(Richard,John)
- Instantiating the universal sentence in all possible ways, we have:
- King(John) Ù Greedy(John) Þ Evil(John)
- King(Richard) Ù
Greedy(Richard) Þ
Evil(Richard)
- King(John)
- Greedy(John)
- Brother(Richard,John)
- The new KB is propositionalized: proposition symbols are
- King(John), Greedy(John),
Evil(John), King(Richard), etc.
|
6
|
- Every FOL KB can be propositionalized so as to preserve entailment
- (A ground sentence is entailed by new KB iff entailed by original KB)
- Idea: propositionalize KB and query, apply resolution, return result
- Problem: with function symbols, there are infinitely many ground terms,
- e.g., Father(Father(Father(John)))
|
7
|
- Theorem: Herbrand (1930). If a sentence α is entailed by an FOL KB,
it is entailed by a finite subset of the propositionalized KB
- Idea: For n = 0 to ∞ do
- create a propositional KB by
instantiating with depth-n terms
- see if α is entailed by
this KB
- Problem: works if α is entailed, loops if α is not entailed
- Theorem: Turing (1936), Church (1936) Entailment for FOL is
semidecidable (algorithms
exist that say yes to every entailed sentence, but no algorithm exists
that also says no to every non-entailed sentence.)
|
8
|
- Propositionalization seems to generate lots of irrelevant sentences.
- E.g., from:
- "x King(x) Ù Greedy(x) Þ Evil(x)
- King(John)
- "y Greedy(y)
- Brother(Richard,John)
- it seems obvious that Evil(John), but propositionalization produces lots
of facts such as Greedy(Richard) that are irrelevant
- With p k-ary predicates and n constants, there are p·nk
instantiations.
|
9
|
- We can get the inference immediately if we can find a substitution θ
such that King(x) and Greedy(x) match King(John) and Greedy(y)
- θ = {x/John,y/John} works
- Unify(α,β) = θ if αθ = βθ
- p q θ
- Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane)
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,OJ)
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y))
- Knows(John,x) Knows(x,OJ)
- Standardizing apart eliminates overlap of variables, e.g., Knows(z17,OJ)
|
10
|
- We can get the inference immediately if we can find a substitution θ
such that King(x) and Greedy(x) match King(John) and Greedy(y)
- θ = {x/John,y/John} works
- Unify(α,β) = θ if αθ = βθ
- p q θ
- Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) {x/Jane}}
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,OJ)
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y))
- Knows(John,x) Knows(x,OJ)
- Standardizing apart eliminates overlap of variables, e.g., Knows(z17,OJ)
|
11
|
- We can get the inference immediately if we can find a substitution θ
such that King(x) and Greedy(x) match King(John) and Greedy(y)
- θ = {x/John,y/John} works
- Unify(α,β) = θ if αθ = βθ
- p q θ
- Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) {x/Jane}}
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,OJ) {x/OJ,y/John}}
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y))
- Knows(John,x) Knows(x,OJ)
- Standardizing apart eliminates overlap of variables, e.g., Knows(z17,OJ)
|
12
|
- We can get the inference immediately if we can find a substitution θ
such that King(x) and Greedy(x) match King(John) and Greedy(y)
- θ = {x/John,y/John} works
- Unify(α,β) = θ if αθ = βθ
- p q θ
- Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) {x/Jane}}
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,OJ) {x/OJ,y/John}}
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y)) {y/John,x/Mother(John)}}
- Knows(John,x) Knows(x,OJ)
- Standardizing apart eliminates overlap of variables, e.g., Knows(z17,OJ)
|
13
|
- We can get the inference immediately if we can find a substitution θ
such that King(x) and Greedy(x) match King(John) and Greedy(y)
- θ = {x/John,y/John} works
- Unify(α,β) = θ if αθ = βθ
- p q θ
- Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) {x/Jane}}
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,OJ) {x/OJ,y/John}}
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y)) {y/John,x/Mother(John)}}
- Knows(John,x) Knows(x,OJ) {fail}
- Standardizing apart eliminates overlap of variables, e.g., Knows(z17,OJ)
|
14
|
- To unify Knows(John,x) and Knows(y,z),
- θ = {y/John, x/z } or θ = {y/John, x/John, z/John}
- The first unifier is more general than the second.
- There is a single most general unifier (MGU) that is unique up to
renaming of variables.
|
15
|
|
16
|
|
17
|
- p1', p2', … , pn', ( p1 Ù p2 Ù … Ù pn Þq)
- qθ
- p1' is King(John) p1
is King(x)
- p2' is Greedy(y) p2
is Greedy(x)
- θ is {x/John,y/John} q is Evil(x)
- q θ is Evil(John)
- GMP used with KB of definite clauses (exactly one positive literal)
- All variables assumed universally quantified
|
18
|
- Need to show that
- p1', …, pn', (p1 Ù … Ù pn
Þ q) ╞ qθ
- provided that pi'θ = piθ for all I
- Lemma: For any sentence p, we have p ╞ pθ by UI
- (p1 Ù … Ù pn Þ q) ╞ (p1 Ù … Ù pn Þ q)θ = (p1θ Ù … Ù pnθ
Þ qθ)
- p1', …, pn' ╞ p1' Ù … Ù pn' ╞ p1'θ Ù … Ù pn'θ
- From 1 and 2, qθ follows by ordinary Modus Ponens
|
19
|
- The law says that it is a crime for an American to sell weapons to
hostile nations. The country
Nono, an enemy of America, has some missiles, and all of its missiles
were sold to it by Colonel West, who is American.
- Prove that Col. West is a criminal
|
20
|
- ... it is a crime for an American to sell weapons to hostile nations:
- American(x) Ù Weapon(y) Ù Sells(x,y,z) Ù Hostile(z) Þ Criminal(x)
- Nono … has some missiles, i.e., $x Owns(Nono,x) Ù Missile(x):
- Owns(Nono,M1) and Missile(M1)
- … all of its missiles were sold to it by Colonel West
- Missile(x) Ù Owns(Nono,x) Þ Sells(West,x,Nono)
- Missiles are weapons:
- An enemy of America counts as "hostile“:
- Enemy(x,America) Þ Hostile(x)
- West, who is American …
- The country Nono, an enemy of America …
|
21
|
|
22
|
|
23
|
|
24
|
|
25
|
- Sound and complete for first-order definite clauses
- Datalog = first-order definite clauses + no functions
- FC terminates for Datalog in finite number of iterations
- May not terminate in general if α is not entailed
- This is unavoidable: entailment with definite clauses is semidecidable
|
26
|
- Incremental forward chaining: no need to match a rule on iteration k if
a premise wasn't added on iteration k-1
- Þ match each rule whose
premise contains a newly added positive literal
- Matching itself can be expensive:
- Database indexing allows O(1) retrieval of known facts
- e.g., query Missile(x) retrieves Missile(M1)
- Forward chaining is widely used in deductive databases
|
27
|
- Colorable() is inferred iff the CSP has a solution
- CSPs include 3SAT as a special case, hence matching is NP-hard
|
28
|
- SUBST(COMPOSE(θ1, θ2), p) = SUBST(θ2,
SUBST(θ1, p))
|
29
|
|
30
|
|
31
|
|
32
|
|
33
|
|
34
|
|
35
|
|
36
|
- Depth-first recursive proof search: space is linear in size of proof
- Incomplete due to infinite loops
- Þ fix by checking current
goal against every goal on stack
- Inefficient due to repeated subgoals (both success and failure)
- Þ fix using caching of
previous results (extra space)
- Widely used for logic programming
|
37
|
- Algorithm = Logic + Control
- Basis: backward chaining with Horn clauses + bells & whistles
- Widely used in Europe, Japan (basis of 5th Generation project)
- Compilation techniques Þ 60
million LIPS
- Program = set of clauses = head :- literal1, … literaln.
- criminal(X) :- american(X), weapon(Y), sells(X,Y,Z), hostile(Z).
- Depth-first, left-to-right backward chaining
- Built-in predicates for arithmetic etc., e.g., X is Y*Z+3
- Built-in predicates that have side effects (e.g., input and output
- predicates, assert/retract predicates)
- Closed-world assumption ("negation as failure")
- e.g., given alive(X) :- not dead(X).
- alive(joe) succeeds if dead(joe) fails
|
38
|
- Appending two lists to produce a third:
- append([],Y,Y).
- append([X|L],Y,[X|Z]) :- append(L,Y,Z).
- query: append(A,B,[1,2]) ?
- answers: A=[] B=[1,2]
- A=[1] B=[2]
- A=[1,2] B=[]
|
39
|
- Full first-order version:
- l1 Ú ··· Ú lk, m1 Ú ··· Ú mn
- (l1 Ú ··· Ú li-1 Ú li+1 Ú ··· Ú lk Ú m1 Ú ··· Ú mj-1
Ú mj+1 Ú ··· Ú mn)θ
- where Unify(li, Ømj) = θ.
- The two clauses are assumed to be standardized apart so that they share
no variables.
- For example,
- ØRich(x) Ú Unhappy(x)
- Rich(Ken)
- Unhappy(Ken)
- with θ = {x/Ken}
- Apply resolution steps to CNF(KB Ù Øα);
complete for FOL
|
40
|
- Everyone who loves all animals is loved by someone:
- "x ["y Animal(y) Þ Loves(x,y)] Þ [$y Loves(y,x)]
- 1. Eliminate biconditionals and implications
- "x [Ø"y ØAnimal(y) Ú
Loves(x,y)] Ú [$y Loves(y,x)]
- 2. Move Ø inwards: Ø"x p ≡ $x Øp, Ø $x p ≡ "x Øp
- "x [$y Ø(ØAnimal(y)
Ú Loves(x,y))] Ú [$y Loves(y,x)]
- "x [$y ØØAnimal(y) Ù
ØLoves(x,y)] Ú [$y Loves(y,x)]
- "x [$y Animal(y) Ù ØLoves(x,y)] Ú [$y Loves(y,x)]
|
41
|
- Standardize variables: each quantifier should use a different one
- "x [$y Animal(y) Ù ØLoves(x,y)] Ú [$z Loves(z,x)]
- Skolemize: a more general form of existential instantiation.
- Each existential variable is replaced by a Skolem function of the
enclosing universally quantified variables:
- "x [Animal(F(x)) Ù ØLoves(x,F(x))]
Ú Loves(G(x),x)
- Drop universal quantifiers:
- [Animal(F(x)) Ù ØLoves(x,F(x))] Ú Loves(G(x),x)
- Distribute Ú over Ù :
- [Animal(F(x)) Ú Loves(G(x),x)] Ù [ØLoves(x,F(x))
Ú Loves(G(x),x)]
|
42
|
|