1
|
- Chapters 7, 8 and 9
- + Prolog Redux
|
2
|
- Enumerative methods
- Resolution in CNF
- Forward and Backward Chaining using Modus Ponens in Horn Form
|
3
|
- Proof methods divide into (roughly) two kinds:
- Application of inference rules
- Legitimate (sound) generation of new sentences from old
- Proof = a sequence of inference rule applications
Can use inference rules as operators in a standard search
algorithm
- Typically require transformation of sentences into a normal form
- Model checking
- truth table enumeration (always exponential in n)
- improved backtracking, e.g., Davis-Putnam-Logemann-Loveland (DPLL)
- heuristic search in model space (sound but incomplete)
- e.g., min-conflicts like hill-climbing algorithms
|
4
|
- Two families of efficient algorithms for propositional inference:
- Complete backtracking search algorithms
- DPLL algorithm (Davis, Putnam, Logemann, Loveland)
- Incomplete local search algorithms
|
5
|
- Determine if an input propositional logic sentence (in CNF) is
satisfiable.
- Improvements over truth table enumeration:
- Early termination
- A clause is true if any literal is true.
- A sentence is false if any clause is false.
- Pure symbol heuristic
- Pure symbol: always appears with the same "sign" in all
clauses.
- e.g., In the three clauses (A Ú ØB), (ØB Ú ØC), (C Ú A), A and B are pure, C is impure.
- Make a pure symbol literal true.
- Unit clause heuristic
- Unit clause: only one literal in the clause
- The only literal in a unit clause must be true.
|
6
|
|
7
|
- Incomplete, local search algorithm
- Evaluation function: The min-conflict heuristic of minimizing the number
of unsatisfied clauses
- Balance between greediness and randomness
|
8
|
|
9
|
- Consider random 3-CNF sentences. e.g.,
- (ØD Ú ØB Ú C) Ù (B Ú ØA Ú ØC) Ù (ØC Ú ØB Ú E) Ù (E Ú ØD Ú B) Ù (B Ú E Ú ØC)
- m = number of clauses
- n = number of symbols
- Hard problems seem to cluster near m/n = 4.3 (critical point)
|
10
|
|
11
|
- Median runtime for 100 satisfiable random 3-CNF sentences, n = 50
|
12
|
- Proof methods divide into (roughly) two kinds:
- Application of inference rules
- Legitimate (sound) generation of new sentences from old
- Proof = a sequence of inference rule applications
Can use inference rules as operators in a standard search
algorithm
- Typically require transformation of sentences into a normal form
- Model checking
- truth table enumeration (always exponential in n)
- improved backtracking, e.g., Davis-Putnam-Logemann-Loveland (DPLL)
- heuristic search in model space (sound but incomplete)
- e.g., min-conflicts like hill-climbing algorithms
|
13
|
- Conjunctive Normal Form (CNF)
- conjunction of disjunctions of
literals
- clauses
- E.g., (A Ú ØB) Ù (B Ú ØC Ú ØD)
- Resolution inference rule (for CNF):
- li Ú… Ú lk, m1 Ú … Ú mn
- li Ú … Ú li-1 Ú li+1 Ú … Ú lk Ú m1 Ú … Ú mj-1
Ú mj+1
Ú... Ú mn
- where li and mj are complementary literals.
- E.g., P1,3 Ú P2,2,
ØP2,2
- P1,3
- Resolution is sound and complete
for propositional logic
|
14
|
- KB = (B1,1 Û (P1,2Ú P2,1)) ÙØ B1,1
- α = ØP1,2 (negate
the premise for proof by refutation)
|
15
|
- Given: (P) Ù (ØP)
- Prove: Z
- Can we prove ØZ using the
givens above?
|
16
|
- Equivalent to a search problem
- KB state = node
- Inference rule application = edge
|
17
|
- Define: KB ├i α = sentence α can be derived
from KB by procedure i
- Soundness: i is sound if whenever KB ├i α, it is
also true that KB╞ α
- Completeness: i is complete if whenever KB╞ α, it is also
true that KB ├i α
- Preview: we will define a logic (first-order logic) which is expressive
enough to say almost anything of interest, and for which there exists a
sound and complete inference procedure.
- That is, the procedure will answer any question whose answer follows
from what is known by the KB.
|
18
|
- Completeness: i is complete if whenever KB╞ α, it is also
true that KB ├i α
- An incomplete inference algorithm cannot reach all possible conclusions
- Equivalent to completeness in search (chapter 3)
|
19
|
- Conjunctive Normal Form (CNF)
- conjunction of disjunctions of
literals
- clauses
- E.g., (A Ú ØB) Ù (B Ú ØC Ú ØD)
- Resolution inference rule (for CNF):
- li Ú… Ú lk, m1 Ú … Ú mn
- li Ú … Ú li-1 Ú li+1 Ú … Ú lk Ú m1 Ú … Ú mj-1
Ú mj+1
Ú... Ú mn
- where li and mj are complementary literals.
- E.g., P1,3 Ú P2,2,
ØP2,2
- P1,3
- Resolution is sound and complete
for propositional logic
|
20
|
- Soundness of resolution inference rule:
- Ø(li Ú … Ú li-1 Ú li+1 Ú … Ú lk)
Þ li
- Ømj Þ (m1 Ú … Ú mj-1
Ú mj+1
Ú... Ú mn)
- Ø(li Ú … Ú li-1 Ú li+1 Ú … Ú lk)
Þ (m1 Ú … Ú mj-1 Ú mj+1 Ú... Ú mn)
- where li and mj are complementary literals.
- What if li and Ømj are false?
- What if li and Ømj are true?
|
21
|
- That is, that resolution can decide the truth value of S
- S = set of clauses
- RC(S) = Resolution closure of S = Set of all clauses that can be derived
from S by the resolution inference rule.
- RC(S) has finite cardinality (finite number of symbols P1, P2,
… Pk), thus resolution refutation must terminate.
|
22
|
- Ground resolution theorem = if S unsatisfiable, RC(S) contains empty
clause.
- Prove by proving contrapositive:
- i.e., if RC(S) doesn’t contain empty clause, S is satisfiable
- Do this by constructing a model:
- For each Pi, if there is a clause in RC(S) containing ØPi and all other
literals in the clause are false, assign Pi = false
- Otherwise Pi = true
- This assignment of Pi is a model for S.
|
23
|
- Given(s)
- Conclusion
- A Þ B, A
- B
- B Ù A
- A
- Rules that allow us to introduce new propositions while preserving truth
values: logically equivalent
- Two Examples:
- Modus Ponens
- And Elimination
|
24
|
- Horn Form (restricted)
- KB = conjunction of Horn clauses
- Horn clause =
- proposition symbol; or
- (conjunction of symbols) Þ symbol
- E.g., C Ù (B Þ A) Ù (C Ù D Þ B)
- Modus Ponens (for Horn Form): complete for Horn KBs
- α1, … ,αn, α1 Ù … Ù αn Þ β
- β
- Can be used with forward chaining or backward chaining.
- These algorithms are very natural and run in linear time
|
25
|
- Idea: fire any rule whose premises are satisfied in the KB,
- add its conclusion to the KB, until query is found
|
26
|
- Forward chaining is sound and complete for Horn KB
|
27
|
|
28
|
|
29
|
|
30
|
|
31
|
|
32
|
|
33
|
|
34
|
|
35
|
- FC derives every atomic sentence that is entailed by KB (only for
clauses in Horn form)
- FC reaches a fixed point (the deductive closure) where no new atomic
sentences are derived
- Consider the final state as a model m, assigning true/false to symbols
- Every clause in the original KB is true in m
- Hence m is a model of KB
- If KB╞ q, q is true in every model of KB, including m
|
36
|
|
37
|
|
38
|
|
39
|
|
40
|
- Reducing first-order inference to propositional inference
- Unification
- Generalized Modus Ponens
- Forward chaining
- Backward chaining
- Resolution
|
41
|
- Every instantiation of a universally quantified sentence is entailed by
it:
- "v α
Subst({v/g}, α)
- for any variable v and ground term g
- E.g., "x King(x) Ù Greedy(x) Þ Evil(x) yields:
- King(John) Ù Greedy(John) Þ
Evil(John)
- King(Richard) Ù Greedy(Richard)
Þ Evil(Richard)
- King(Father(John)) Ù Greedy(Father(John))
Þ Evil(Father(John))
- .
- .
- .
|
42
|
- For any sentence α, variable v, and constant symbol k that does not
appear elsewhere in the knowledge base:
- $v α
- Subst({v/k}, α)
- E.g., $x Crown(x) Ù OnHead(x,John) yields:
- Crown(C1) Ù OnHead(C1,John)
- provided C1 is a new constant symbol, called a Skolem
constant
|
43
|
- Suppose the KB contains just the following:
- "x King(x) Ù Greedy(x) Þ Evil(x)
- King(John)
- Greedy(John)
- Brother(Richard,John)
- Instantiating the universal sentence in all possible ways, we have:
- King(John) Ù Greedy(John) Þ Evil(John)
- King(Richard) Ù
Greedy(Richard) Þ
Evil(Richard)
- King(John)
- Greedy(John)
- Brother(Richard,John)
- The new KB is propositionalized: proposition symbols are
- King(John), Greedy(John),
Evil(John), King(Richard), etc.
|
44
|
- Every FOL KB can be propositionalized so as to preserve entailment
- (A ground sentence is entailed by new KB iff entailed by original KB)
- Idea: propositionalize KB and query, apply resolution, return result
- Problem: with function symbols, there are infinitely many ground terms,
- e.g., Father(Father(Father(John)))
|
45
|
- Theorem: Herbrand (1930). If a sentence α is entailed by an FOL KB,
it is entailed by a finite subset of the propositionalized KB
- Idea: For n = 0 to ∞ do
- create a propositional KB by
instantiating with depth-n terms
- see if α is entailed by
this KB
- Problem: works if α is entailed, loops if α is not entailed
- Theorem: Turing (1936), Church (1936) Entailment for FOL is
semi-decidable (algorithms exist that say yes to every entailed
sentence, but no algorithm exists that also says no to every
non-entailed sentence.)
|
46
|
- Propositionalization seems to generate lots of irrelevant sentences.
- E.g., from:
- "x King(x) Ù Greedy(x) Þ Evil(x)
- King(John)
- "y Greedy(y)
- Brother(Richard,John)
- it seems obvious that Evil(John), but propositionalization produces lots
of facts such as Greedy(Richard) that are irrelevant
- With p k-ary predicates and n constants, there are p·nk
instantiations.
|
47
|
- We can get the inference immediately if we can find a substitution θ
such that King(x) and Greedy(x) match King(John) and Greedy(y)
- θ = {x/John,y/John} works
- Unify(α,β) = θ if αθ = βθ
- p q θ
- Knows(John,x) Knows(John,Jane) {x/Jane}}
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,OJ) {x/OJ,y/John}}
- Knows(John,x) Knows(y,Mother(y)) {y/John,x/Mother(John)}}
- Knows(John,x) Knows(x,OJ) {fail}
- Standardizing apart eliminates overlap of variables, e.g., Knows(z17,OJ)
|
48
|
- To unify Knows(John,x) and Knows(y,z),
- θ = {y/John, x/z } or θ = {y/John, x/John, z/John}
- The first unifier is more general than the second.
- There is a single most general unifier (MGU) that is unique up to
renaming of variables.
|
49
|
|
50
|
|
51
|
- p1', p2', … , pn', ( p1 Ù p2 Ù … Ù pn Þq)
- qθ
- p1' is King(John) p1
is King(x)
- p2' is Greedy(y) p2
is Greedy(x)
- θ is {x/John,y/John} q is Evil(x)
- q θ is Evil(John)
- GMP used with KB of definite clauses (exactly one positive literal)
- All variables assumed universally quantified
|
52
|
- Need to show that
- p1', …, pn', (p1 Ù … Ù pn
Þ q) ╞ qθ
- provided that pi'θ = piθ for all I
- Lemma: For any sentence p, we have p ╞ pθ by UI
- (p1 Ù … Ù pn Þ q) ╞ (p1 Ù … Ù pn Þ q)θ = (p1θ Ù … Ù pnθ
Þ qθ)
- p1', …, pn' ╞ p1' Ù … Ù pn' ╞ p1'θ Ù … Ù pn'θ
- From 1 and 2, qθ follows by ordinary Modus Ponens
|
53
|
- The law says that it is a crime for an American to sell weapons to
hostile nations. The country
Nono, an enemy of America, has some missiles, and all of its missiles
were sold to it by Colonel West, who is American.
- Prove that Col. West is a criminal
|
54
|
- ... it is a crime for an American to sell weapons to hostile nations:
- American(x) Ù Weapon(y) Ù Sells(x,y,z) Ù Hostile(z) Þ Criminal(x)
- Nono … has some missiles, i.e., $x Owns(Nono,x) Ù Missile(x):
- Owns(Nono,M1) and Missile(M1)
- … all of its missiles were sold to it by Colonel West
- Missile(x) Ù Owns(Nono,x) Þ Sells(West,x,Nono)
- Missiles are weapons:
- An enemy of America counts as "hostile“:
- Enemy(x,America) Þ Hostile(x)
- West, who is American …
- The country Nono, an enemy of America …
|
55
|
|
56
|
|
57
|
|
58
|
|
59
|
- Sound and complete for first-order definite clauses
- Datalog = first-order definite clauses + no functions
- FC terminates for Datalog in finite number of iterations
- May not terminate in general if α is not entailed
- This is unavoidable: entailment with definite clauses is semidecidable
|
60
|
- Incremental forward chaining: no need to match a rule on iteration k if
a premise wasn't added on iteration k-1
- Þ match each rule whose
premise contains a newly added positive literal
- Matching itself can be expensive:
- Database indexing allows O(1) retrieval of known facts
- e.g., query Missile(x) retrieves Missile(M1)
- Forward chaining is widely used in deductive databases
|
61
|
- SUBST(COMPOSE(θ1, θ2), p) = SUBST(θ2,
SUBST(θ1, p))
|
62
|
|
63
|
|
64
|
|
65
|
|
66
|
|
67
|
|
68
|
|
69
|
- Q: which model do you think
Prolog uses for inference?
|
70
|
- Depth-first recursive proof search: space is linear w.r.t. size of proof
- Incomplete due to infinite loops
- Þ fix by checking current
goal against every goal on stack
- Inefficient due to repeated subgoals (both success and failure)
- Þ fix using caching of
previous results (extra space)
|
71
|
- Prolog needs to choose which goal to pursue first, although logically it
doesn’t matter. Why?
- Treats goals in order, leftmost first.
- A :- B,C,D.
- B :- E,F.
- -? A.
- B is tried first, then C, then
D.
- E and F are pushed onto the
stack, before C and D. Why?
|
72
|
- Prolog also needs to choose which clause to pursue first.
- Treats clauses in order, top-most first.
- G.
- A :- B,C,D.
- B :- E,F.
- B :- G.
- To satisfy goal B, prolog tries
E,F before G.
|
73
|
- Order of Prolog clauses and goals crucial, can affect running times
immensely
- Order of goals tell which get executed first
- Order of clauses tell which control branches are tried first.
|
74
|
- likes(hari,X) :- makan(X), consumes(hari,X).
- likes(min,X) :- likes(hari,X).
- makan(meeSiam).
- makan(rojak).
- minum(rootBeerFloat).
- consumes(hari,meeSiam).
|
75
|
- Whew! That was a loooooooong lecture.
What did we learn?
- Enumeration: DPLL rules are similar to CSP heuristics.
- Resolution is proof by refutation, used in PL.
- Other forms of reasoning: Modus Ponens which requires Horn form.
- FOL uses unification to find solutions, requires Skolem constants and
functions.
- Forward (undirected) and Backward (directed) chaining patterns to apply
an inference mechanism.
|